|
Partially Resolving the
Tension Between
Omniscience
and Free Will:
A Mathematical Argument
Joseph Fulda is a freelance writer living in New York City. He
is the author of Eight Steps Towards Libertarianism.
One of the thorniest and most intriguing problems in the philosophy
of religion has been the tension between man’s free will and God’s
omniscience—or more exactly, His foreknowledge. For if He knows in
advance what we will do, in what sense can our doing it be free? A
standard answer, dating to at least Maimonides, is that the phrase “in
advance” is misused. What God knows, He knows timelessly: time is a
measure of change in the material and the corporeal; God is outside the
realm of the material and the corporeal: His knowledge is therefore
qualitatively different from ours and exists, as it were, above and
without time. This answer seems to work around the problem rather than
addressing it squarely.
In this article, we sketch a partial resolution to this classical
problem by concentrating not so much on God’s omniscience as on His
omnipotence. Of course, His omnipotence poses no direct problem for free
will, since it is understood that any agents that He has decided to make
autonomous will, up to the limits of their autonomy, be free actors. But
while God does not control the autonomy of free-willed agents, He
certainly does control the environment within which they act; in fact, He
controls it omni potently, that is, completely.
In an article in Mind, “The Mathematical Pull of
Temptation,” I put forth a theory of temptation that can be used to show
how God’s omnipotence matters, how it can be used to rescue His
omniscience in the fact of free-willed agents. Let us briefly review this
theory.
It is assumed by preachers and laymen alike that our steadfastness
when presented with an object of temptation depends on (a) our character,
and (b) the tempting strength of the object. To paraphrase Henry Ward
Beecher on character and temptation: Temptations without imply
desires within. A man ought not to say “How powerfully the devil
tempts,” but “How strongly I am tempted.” As for the pull of the
object, it is the conventional view that the stronger it is, the more
likely we are to succumb and the less likely we are to resist.
We put forward an alternative account of temptation that suggests
that both character and the object of temptation may not, in some cases,
be considerations, let alone the dominant considerations, in explaining
behavior in the face of temptation.
We arranged a simple thought experiment, which we referred to as
“the red case.” A man is placed in a solitary room with a red button
and nothing else. For twenty-four hours, he remains alone in that room.
Pressing the red button at any time initiates a sequence of sinful events
that will culminate in his obtaining the object of his temptation. However
slight the pull of the temptation behind the red button, it is a man of
very rare will who will be able to resist its continuous lure. The man,
that is, is as weak as weakest moment.
We also arranged the converse thought experiment, which we referred
to as “the black case.” A man has already initiated a sequence of
events that will result in his obtaining the object of his temptation.
Now, he is placed in a solitary room with a black button and nothing else.
For twenty-four hours, he remains alone in that room. Pressing the black
button just once disrupts the sequence of events that would otherwise
produce for him the object of his temptation, and the temptation will have
been successfully resisted. However strong the pull of the tempting
object, the pull of conscience nearly guarantees that the man will leave
his confinement having pressed the black button. The man, that is, is as
strong as his strongest moment.
We continued by presenting the mathematics behind these intuitions.
Even if the man in the red case is a very good man, one who normally
resists temptation, and even if we can quantify this judgment by saying
that a priori, and without our intervention and the lure of
the red button, he would succumb to a single presentation of the tempting
object only one time in one hundred (and this number does
depend on the object), simple probability calculations show that for the
4800 presentations in the red case he is virtually certain (1 - .994800)
to succumb. Likewise, even if the man in the black case is very easily
swayed by the slightest of desires, and even if we can quantify this
judgment by saying that a priori, and without our
intervention and the pull of the black button, he would succumb to a
single presentation of the tempting object fully ninety-nine times in one
hundred (and, again, this number does depend on the object),
simple probability calculations show that for the 4800 chances he will
have to resist a single presentation he is virtually certain (l - .994800)
to resist it. Notice that in either case switching .99 and .01 would make no
perceptible difference for any significant number of opportunities to
succumb or resist.
Now, God’s omnipotence places Him in control of the opportunity
structure of the world with which we are all daily faced, while man’s
autonomous will places him (primarily) in control of the likelihood of his
succumbing or resisting an opportunity (what we call character), so the
man-God interaction comes down to ab, with man in control of a
and God in control of b, and as everyone knows, b dominates a.
That is the crux of the (partial) resolution of the tension between
omniscience and free will: God sets up the opportunity structure within
which we sin or do good and He can force an outcome out of even truly free
actors, and even when He does not force an outcome, it may be plain to Him
as a simple result of His knowledge of both a and b and his
complete control over b. Since we would not expect forcing or
prior-knowledge-without-forcing for each of man’s actions, our solution
remains partial, but it does suggest an avenue of thought and research on
this millennia-old problem.
Ω
We would like to thank the following people for their generous
contributions (made up to July 15, 2003) to the publication of this
journal: George E. Andrews, Lee R. Ashmun, Frank J. Bartz, Alexis Bayard,
Charles Benscheidt, James L. Bililie, Robert P. Bringer, Georgia Buchta,
William L. Burns, Frances G. Campbell, Irma I. Clark, Eugene H. Donovan,
Nicholas Falco, Edwin J. Feulner, Richard G. Frost, James R. Gaines, Gary
Gillespie, William R. Grant, Dick Herreid, Jaren E. Hiller, Thomas E.
Humphreys, David Ihle, Donald C. Ingram, O. Walter Johnson, Robert R.
Johnson, Frank G. Kenski, A. R. Kircher, Gloria Knoblauch, Donald Krier,
James F. Lammers, Benjamin H. Lane, Donald G. Lee, Calvin T. Lucy, Thomas
D. MacStocker, Daniel Maher, Thomas J. McGreevy, David P. and Barbara R.
Mitchel, Leonore E. Moberg, Dwight D. Murphey, Harry Neuwirth, Marsha
Nickels, William J. Nolan, Frances S. Richardson, Mark and Beth Richter,
Howard J. Romanek, Millard H. Ruether, H. Richard Schumacher, Al Shane,
Michael Stiennon, Clifford W. Stone, Dennis J. Sullivan, Mary H. Sunberg,
Michael S. Swisher, Doug Tice, Jack E. Turner, Johanna Visser, Rodney G.
Weiler, Robert D. Wells, George M. Wheatley, James W. Williams. |
||
[ Who We Are | Authors | Archive | Subscribtion | Search | Contact Us ] © Copyright St.Croix Review 2002 |