|
The Soul of the Democrat
Thomas Martin
Thomas Martin teaches in the
Department of Philosophy at the University of Nebraska at Kearney. You may
contact Thomas Martin at: martint@unk.edu. [H]e lives on, yielding day by day to the desire at
hand. Sometimes he drinks heavily while listening to the flute; at other times,
he drinks only water and is on a diet; sometimes he goes in for physical training;
at other times, he’s idle and neglects everything; and sometimes he even
occupies himself with what he takes to be philosophy. He often engages in
politics, leaping up from his seat and saying and doing whatever comes to mind.
If he happens to admire soldiers, he’s carried in that direction, if
money-makers, in that one. There’s neither order nor necessity in his
life, but he calls it pleasant, free, and blessedly happy, and he follows it
for as long as he lives. You’ve perfectly described the life of a man who
believes in legal equality. These words are from
Plato and are found in book eight of Republic in which the constitutions of the democratic city and
the soul of the democratic man are described. Of the five constitutions of the
city-states in Republic, and the
individuals housed within each, which are presented in descending order from
the highest to the lowest, the democratic state is fourth from the top, one
step away from tyranny, which is the city state and man ruled by erotic love. Plato understands the
soul as tripart: reason, spirit and desire. Reason and desire are understood as
the rational and irrational parts of the soul; the former part
“calculates,” and the latter part “lusts, hungers, thirsts,
and gets excited by other appetites.” Man by nature has an end, telos, at which he may aim if he is to be fulfilled.
Man’s end is known by reason, and he is a creature who lives by ideas. A
just man, a man in full, is governed by the rational part of his soul which
directs him to act in a virtuous manner, such that every part of him performs
its proper function while reason controls the inferior parts of his nature. The
just state is realized when a person is performing his proper function and not
meddling where he does not belong. The just state in Republic is the ideal state, which is created by
Socrates’ dialectic discussion with Glaucon, Polemarchus, Adeimantus,
Thrasymachus, and the other young men who are present for the discussion of how
justice works in the soul of man. (The reader, obviously, is present, if, that
is, he is engaged.) The ideal state, the Aristocracy, has never existed, but
the virtues on which it is founded, justice, wisdom, courage and moderation,
are grasped by reason and do exist in the souls and actions of man. This state
serves as a point of reference from which to set the extreme constitution of
tyranny, its opposite, as well as the intermediate states of the timocrat,
oligarch, and the democrat. It is helpful when
reading Plato to remember that man is not an animal by nature, but part of him
is like an animal. Let me explain. A Gordon setter is by nature a soft-mouthed
dog, ideal for retrieving birds because it does not sink its teeth into the bird.
The Gordon setter is very alert, interested and aggressive. It is a responsive
gun dog, and an eager-to-please dog in the home. A Gordon setter will not
naturally retrieve birds, but it can easily be trained to do so because it is
within its potential to do so. If, that is, the Gordon setter has a trainer. Man is like an animal
in that he also needs instruction to reach his potential. Man, like a dog,
comes in a variety of breeds; however, being well-bred for a man is different
than having the pedigree of a Gordon setter. Man’s pedigree is revealed
by the performance of his function, which has been handed down to him in the
stories of his virtuous ancestors. Unlike a Gordon setter, man does not inherit
his pedigree; it is something he achieves by performing his function. Each person has a
variety of functions. If he is a cobbler (obviously, an ancient example as
cobblers have gone the way of the bare feet that stomped the grapes), he makes
shoes, and if he is a virtuous cobbler, he makes good shoes. A cobbler has the
various functions, of a husband, father, soldier, neighbor, friend and like
relationships in which he finds himself. Man as a cobbler is a creature who
becomes himself--or not--in his relationships with the leather and his
community. Being a virtuous human is a question of being
well-ordered. In this case, order is a word that signifies a harmonious
arrangement, first, in the soul, which is the moral order, and then in the
city-state, which is the constitutional order. Reason is the ruling element in
the soul that grasps moral principles, the enduring standards, and the moral
norms of man’s nature that are necessary for self-examination. Inasmuch
as the moral principles are enduring, they are divine and not the creation of
man. Which brings us back to the soul of a democrat, a
free spirit whose soul is not guided by moral principle; he lacks the ability
to distinguish higher from lower, right from wrong, and good from evil. In the
democratic soul, reason is the handmaid of desire, the inferior part of
man’s nature; thus, he “lives on, yielding day by day to the desire
at hand.” This democrat uses his intellect to rationalize whatever his
desires crave at the moment; he cannot truly discriminate between his necessary
and unnecessary desires. In effect, each desire has a say, and all desires are
treated as equal. This is a soul Plato ironically describes as being . . . a pleasant constitution, which lacks rulers but
not variety and which distributes a sort of equality to both equals and
unequals alike. The democratic
city-state is similar to the democratic soul: everyone is treated equally. At
first glance it seems to be a fine constitution, like a coat embroidered with
every kind of ornament because it has every kind of character type. With such
diversity, could it be anything but wonderful? However, in the city and the
souls which live by the idea of treating equals and unequals as equal,
condemned criminals walk about freely and foreigners have the rights of
citizens, but the obligations of the citizens to vote or serve on juries and in
the military are such that they may do so if they feel like it. The democratic soul turns inward and
neglects its public responsibility; in fact, it does not have a sense of
community. It has nothing in common with those within its city, other than
being guided by desires that cry to be heard and feel the need to be satisfied. Thus, the democratic soul, as well as the democratic
city, lacks “ruler” and is opposed to any form of authority other
than the pressing momentary urge. So, . . . he drinks heavily while listening to the flute; at
other times, he drinks only water and is on a diet; sometimes he goes in for
physical training; at other times, he’s idle and neglects everything; and
sometimes he even occupies himself with what he takes to be philosophy. His mind is not led by
moral principles (an example of principle given at the beginning of Republic is “you should not return a harm with a
harm”) and he cannot focus upon an ideal and use it as the point for his
actions. The democratic father, for example, refuses to accept a guiding
principle into his soul, as it would be an infringement upon the equality of
his children’s right to fulfill their immediate desires. Thus, . . . a father accustoms himself to behave like a
child and fear his sons, while the son behaves like a father, feeling neither
shame nor fear in front of his parents, in order to be free. The democratic soul
sees freedom as being “free from” as opposed to “free
to,” so he is “free from” responsibility and does as he feels at the moment. It is important to notice that the
father behaves like a child; the
emphasis is on behave, as the father does not “act,” for to act one
needs to “know” what he is doing, making him the author of his act.
The democratic father behaves
because he is motivated by desire and not by principle. He exercises until it
becomes painful, boring, or another desire clamors to be satisfied. The son behaves like a father; he does not act like a father but becomes like a father because of
the demanding nature, or authority, of the adolescent desires rising up in his
soul at any moment. As the son is defiant of authority, all tradition, the way
of his ancestors, is denied as being outdated and confining to his freedom to
serve his desires. The
democratic teacher, next in line in the tradition of authority over the young,
fares equally as well as the father, and . . . [a] teacher in such a community is afraid of
his students and flatters them, while the students despise their teachers . . .
The teacher is afraid
of students because he has no right to impose his knowledge--all opinions being
equal--upon students. Furthermore, the student despises his teachers for
presuming to think that they know more than the students. It is best for
students, in the words of Bob Dylan, to let their teachers know what they have
told their parents, Come
mothers and fathers Throughout
the land And
don’t criticize What
you can’t understand Your
sons and your daughters Are
beyond your command. The democratic ruler, ascending in authority, in
order to gain his position, need only tell the citizens “that he wishes
the majority well,” which
means the citizens in the democratic state will be free to continue doing
whatever they desire, be it reading Milton or looking at website pornography,
being faithfully married or committing adultery, paying taxes or not, having
children or aborting babies, helping the sick and aged or euthanizing them--it
is all the same. Thus . . . the
person who is honored and considered clever and wise in important matters by
such badly governed cities is the one who serves them most pleasantly, indulges
them, flatters them, anticipates their wishes, and is clever in fulfilling
them. The soul of the
democratic man is in turmoil as reason is subservient to a multitude of
desires, unrestrained by the virtue of moderation, and above authority. The
words that correctly name the virtues have been distorted by this character. Doing battle and controlling things themselves,
won’t they call reverence foolishness and moderation cowardice, abusing
them and casting them out beyond the frontiers like disenfranchised exiles? And
won’t they persuade the young man that measured and orderly expenditure
is boorish and mean, and, joining with many useless desires, won’t they
expel it across the border. . . . They proceed to return insolence, anarchy,
extravagance, and shamelessness from exile and give them fine names, calling
insolence good breeding, anarchy freedom, extravagance magnificence, and
shamelessness courage. What we now have is an
uncontrollable adolescent, refusing authority and revering nothing. The
distortions of his head visit the body and, as he ages, lacking self-control,
his health deteriorates, so he thinks the function of physicians is to restore
that which he abused. All the money spent on healing is of no use, so he ends
up blaming the abysmal quality of physicians as the source of his feeling ill. And isn’t it amusing that they consider their
worst enemy to be the person who tells them the truth, namely, that until they
give up drunkenness, overeating, lechery, and idleness, no medicine, cautery,
or surgery, no charms, amulets, or anything else of that kind will do them any
good? The democratic soul is
obsessed with the idea of tolerance, which becomes a virtue, so it naively
treats all desires as deserving equal attention. This is the intellectual
position; however, when desire has replaced right-minded reason in the soul,
what the head thinks to be the case is secondary to the demands of the body.
So, while the head is tolerant of all desires being equal, the depraved desire
of erotic love, the antithesis of philosophy that is the love of wisdom,
consumes the soul. The element of authority is impotent in the soul of a
democrat so .
. . he’s idle and neglects everything; and sometimes he even occupies
himself with what he takes to be philosophy. The perversion of a
democrat’s attempt at philosophy is seen when Glaucon, Polemarchus,
Adeimantus, Thrasymachus, and the other young men of the dialogue, as
“reasonable men,” distort the ancient proverb “Friends have
all things in common” to deduce that women and children are possessions
and friends ought to share their possessions. Under the spell of
erotic love, they further decide that the best men (which they all assume
themselves to be) ought to have sex with the best women as frequently as
possible. To keep the women from becoming attached to their children (which is
the natural way to act) the women are treated as equals and now share
occupations alongside the men. Their children of the best men and best women
are housed in a “rearing pen,” the ancient equivalent of a day-care
center, “to insure that no mother knows her child.” True to form
the children of the worst parents are left outside the rearing pen to die. The
father is oblivious to his children, as those driven by erotic love feel no
responsibility for the offspring of their actions. (This is decided upon,
obviously, without the young men consulting the mothers, sisters, or women of the state.) The final descent into
the tyrannical nature of erotic love is seen in the confrontation between
Socrates and Glaucon, the pedophiliac, to show how the egalitarian soul is
caught in a swoon before the object of its depravity that consumes its
insatiable lust. But it isn’t appropriate for an erotically inclined man to forget
that all boys in the bloom of youth pique the interest of the lover of boys and
arouse him and that all seem worthy of his care and pleasure. Or isn’t
that the way you people behave to fine and beautiful boys? You praise a
snub-nosed one as cute, a hook-nosed one you say is regal, one in between is
well proportioned, dark ones look manly, and pale ones are children of the
gods. And as for a honey-colored boy, do you think that this very term is
anything but the euphemistic coinage of a lover who found it easy to tolerate
shallowness, provided it was accompanied by the bloom of youth? In other word,
you find all kinds of terms and excuses so as not to reject anyone whose flower
is in bloom. Such is the
destructive nature of erotic love; first it destroys the love between man and
woman, then turns women into common possessions and resolves the dilemma of
unwanted children by lodging them in “rearing pens,” and finally
erotic love accepts the sterile act of fornicating with the same sex as in
Glaucon’s homosexual passion for any boy in “the bloom of
youth.” At this point the descent of the democratic soul is complete. Extreme freedom can’t be expected to lead to
anything but a change to extreme slavery, whether for a private individual or
for a city. This type of democracy
is not a virtuous form of government inasmuch as it is one step away from
tyranny. Lacking self-restraint and transfixed by the idea of the equality of
both equals and unequals alike, the soul is fractioned, each appetite having a
will and clamoring to be heard. Ultimately, the strongest desire of erotic love
gives license to mad sensuality having its way in a soul that is a slave to its
“mad masters.” And so it goes. * “A man should never
be ashamed to own that he has been in the wrong, which is but saying . . . that
he is wiser today than he was yesterday.” –Alexander Pope |
||
[ Who We Are | Authors | Archive | Subscription | Search | Contact Us ] © Copyright St.Croix Review 2002 |